3.5 Conditioning Inner and Outer Measures


3.5 Conditioning Inner and Outer Measures

How should conditioning be done for inner and outer measures? More precisely, suppose that μ is a probability measure defined on a subalgebra of . What should μ*(V | U) and μ*(V | U) be if U, V ? The first thought might be to take the obvious analogue of the definitions of μ*(V) and μ*(V), and define, for example, μ*(V | U) to be min{μ(V|U): U′⊇U, V′⊇V, U, V }. However, this definition is easily seen to be quite unreasonable. For example, if U and V are in , it may not give μ(V | U). For example, suppose that V U, V , and μ(V) < μ(U) < 1. Taking V = V and U = W, it follows from this definition that μ*(V | U) μ(V). Since μ(V) < μ(V | U), this means that μ*(V | U) < μ(V | U). This certainly doesn't seem reasonable.

One way of fixing this might be to take U to be a subset of U in the definition of μ*, that is, taking μ*(V | U) to be min{μ(V|U) : U U, V V, U, V }. But this choice also has problems. For example, if V U, U, V , and μ(U V) > 0, then according to this definition, μ*(V | U) μ(V | U V) = 0. Again, this does not seem right.

The actual definition is motivated by Theorem 2.3.3. Given a measure μ on , let μ consist of all the extensions of μ to . Then for U, V such that μ*(U) > 0, define

Are there expressions for μ*(V | U) and μ*(V | U) in terms of expressions such as μ*(V U), μ*(U), analogous to the standard expression when all sets are measurable? One might guess that μ*(V | U) = μ*(V U)/μ*(U), taking the best approximation from below for the numerator and the best approximation from above for the denominator. This does not quite work. For suppose that μ*(U) < μ*(U). Then μ*(U)/μ*(U) < 1, while it is immediate that μ*(U | U) = 1.

Although this choice gives inappropriate answers, something similar does much better. The idea for μ*(V | U) is to have μ*(V U) in the numerator, as expected. For the denominator, instead of using μ*(U), the set U is partitioned into V U and V U. For V U, the inner measure is used, since this is the choice made in the numerator. It is only for V U that the outer measure is used.

Theorem 3.5.1

start example

Suppose that μ*(U) > 0. Then

end example

Proof I consider μ*(V | U) here. The argument for μ*(V | U) is almost identical and is left to the reader (Exercise 3.13). First, suppose that μ*(V U) = 0. Then it should be clear that μ′(V U) = 0, and so μ′(U) = μ′(V U), for all μ′ μ. Thus μ′(V | U) = 1 for all μ′ μ with μ′(U) > 0, and so μ*(V | U) = 1. (This is true even if μ*(V U) = 0.)

To show that (3.4) works if μ*(V U) > 0, I first show that if μ′ is an extension of μ to such that μ(U) > 0, then

By Theorem 2.3.3, μ*(V U) μ′(V U) and μ′(V U) μ*(V U). By additivity, it follows that

In general, if x + y > 0, y 0, and x x, then x/(x + y) x/(x + y) (Exercise 3.13). Thus,

It remains to show that this bound is tight, that is, that there exists an extension μ1 such that . This is also left as an exercise (Exercise 3.13).

It is immediate from Theorem 3.5.1 that μ*(U | U) = μ*(U | U) = 1, as expected. Perhaps more interesting is the observation that if U is measurable, then μ*(V | U) = μ*(V U)/μ(U) and μ*(V | U) = μ*(V U)/μ(U). This follows easily from the fact that

(Exercise 3.14). The following example shows that the formulas for inner and outer measure also give intuitively reasonable answers in concrete examples:

Example 3.5.2

start example

What happens if the three-prisoners puzzle is represented using non-measurable sets to capture the unknown probability that the jailer will say b given that a is pardoned? Let consist of all the sets that can be formed by taking unions of lives -a, lives -b, and lives -c (where is considered to be the empty union); that is, lives -a, lives -b, and lives -c form a basis for . Since neither of the singleton sets {(a, b)} and {(a, c)} is in , no probability must be assigned to the event that the jailer will say b (resp., c) if a is pardoned. Note that all the measures in J agree on the sets in . Let μJ be the measure on that agrees with each of the measures in J. An easy computation shows that

  • (μJ)*(lives-a says-b) = (μJ)*({(a, b)}) = 0 (since the only element of contained in {(a, b)} is the empty set);

  • (μJ)*(lives-a says-b) = (μJ)*({(a, b)}) = 1/3; and

  • (μJ)*(lives-a says-b) = (μJ)*(lives-a says-b) = μ({(c, b)}) = 1/3.

It follows from the arguments in Example 3.3.1 that

Just as Theorem 3.5.1 says, these equations give the lower and upper conditional probabilities of the set J conditioned on the jailer saying b.

end example




Reasoning About Uncertainty
Reasoning about Uncertainty
ISBN: 0262582597
EAN: 2147483647
Year: 2005
Pages: 140

flylib.com © 2008-2017.
If you may any questions please contact us: flylib@qtcs.net