Exercises


  • 9.1 This exercise shows that the plausibility measures Pl1 and Pl2 considered in Section 9.1 can be obtained using the construction preceding Theorem 8.4.12.

    1. Show that Pl1 is the plausibility measure obtained from the probability sequence (μ1, μ2, μ3, ) defined in Section 9.1, using the construction preceding Theorem 8.4.12.

    2. Define a probability sequence (μ1, μ2, μ3, ) from which Pl2 is obtained using the construction preceding Theorem 8.4.12.

  • 9.2 Prove Proposition 9.1.1.

  • 9.3 Prove Proposition 9.1.2.

  • 9.4 Prove Proposition 9.1.3.

  • 9.5 Show that in an SDP system (, a, π), if the prior Pla on runs that generates a satisfies Pl4 and Pl5, then so does the agent's plausibility space Pla(r, m) at each point (r, m).

  • 9.6 Show that a BCS is a synchronous system satisfying CONS in which the agent has perfect recall.

  • * 9.7 This exercise expands on Example 9.3.1 and shows that AGM-style belief revision can be understood as conditioning, using a conditional probability measure. As in Example 9.3.1, fix a finite set Φ of primitive propositions and a consequence relation for Prop(Φ).

    1. Show that there is a single formula σ such that iff σ φ is a propositional tautology.

    2. As in Example 9.3.1, let M = (W, 2W, 2W , μ, π) be a simple conditional probability structure, where π is such that (i) (M, w) σ for all w W and (ii) if σ ψ is satisfiable, then there is some world w W such that (M, w) ψ. Let K ={ψ : μ([[ψ]]M) = 1}. If [[φ]]M , define K φ ={ψ : μ([[ψ]]M|[[φ]]M) = 1}; if [[φ]]M = , define K φ = Cl(false). Show that this definition of revision satisfies R1–8.

    3. Given a revision operator satisfying R1–8 (with respect to and a belief set K Cl(false), show that there exists a simple conditional probability space MK = (W, 2W, 2W , μK, π) such that (i) K ={ψ : μ([[ψ]]M) = 1} and (ii) if K φ Cl(false), then K φ ={ψ : μ([[ψ]]M | [[φ]]M) = 1}.

    Note that part (b) essentially shows that every conditional probability measure defines a belief revision operator, and part (c) essentially shows that every belief revision operator can be viewed as arising from a conditional probability measure on an appropriate space.

  • 9.8 Construct a BCS satisfying REV1 and REV2 that has the properties required in Example 9.3.3. Extend this example to one that satisfies REV1 and REV2 but violates R7 and R8.

  • 9.9 Show that if BCS1–3 hold and sa φ is a local state in , then [sa] [φ].

  • 9.10 Prove Lemma 9.3.4.

  • 9.11 Show that 1 .

  • * 9.12 Fill in the missing details of Theorem 9.3.5. In particular, show that the definition of s, a satisfies R1–8 if K Bel(, sa) or sa φ is not a local state in , and provide the details of the proof that R7 and R8 hold if K = Bel(, sa) and sa φ is a local state in .

  • 9.13 Show that the BCS constructed in Example 9.3.6 is in .

  • * 9.14 Prove Theorem 9.3.7.

  • 9.15 Prove Theorem 9.4.1.

  • * 9.16 Complete the proof of Theorem 9.4.2(b) by showing that R7 and R8 hold.

  • 9.17 This exercise relates the postulates and property (9.9).

    1. Show that (9.9) follows from R3, R4, R7, and R8.

    2. Show that if BS satisfies R2 and ψ BS(E φ), then e (φ ψ).

    3. Describe a system I that satisfies (9.9) and not R9.

    4. Show that R8 follows from R2, R4 and R9.

  • * 9.18 Complete the proof of Theorem 9.5.1. Moreover, show that (, BS) satisfies R1–9, thus proving Theorem 9.5.2.

  • * 9.19 Complete the proof of Theorem 9.5.3.

  • * 9.20 Complete the proof of Theorem 9.6.2. (The difficulty here, as suggested in the text, is making Pl algebraic.)




Reasoning About Uncertainty
Reasoning about Uncertainty
ISBN: 0262582597
EAN: 2147483647
Year: 2005
Pages: 140

flylib.com © 2008-2017.
If you may any questions please contact us: flylib@qtcs.net